Behaviorism
Trumps Cognitive Psychology?
Some
of the most subtle insights about Behaviorism are embedded in a joke
heard on <bloggingheads.tv>. Partners were making love and,
afterwards, one said, “I know it was good for you; how was it for
me?” In 1990, the year of his death, B.F. Skinner gave the keynote
address at the annual meeting of APA. He must have recognized that
this speech would be his final opportunity to critique the discipline
of psychology, and to make his case for operant conditioning, in
front of a large audience. Perhaps the most controversial comment
that he made in the hour long lecture was, “Cognitive science is
the creationism of psychology.” Clearly, Skinner never renounced
“radical behaviorism” nor, apparently, did he modify his views in
response to critics such as Noam Chomsky and psychologists. In some
ways, though clinical psychologists have dominated the APA for more
than two decades, disagreements remain about what theoretical and
empirical approaches are the most powerful (in a statistical sense)
predictors of animal (including, human) behavior. A cognitive
orientation currently dominates most departments of psychology in the
United States. Nonetheless, most patterns of overt behavior may be
expressed “automatically” in the sense that conscious and aware
thought has not, unless I am mistaken, been shown to be a typical
precursor to action patterns (motor patterns, “behavior”). As a
demonstration of the last point, I developed a classroom exercise
requiring students to think of a simple activity (e.g., cooking an
egg, washing dishes, braiding hair), dividing the activity into motor
patterns, and thinking through each component of the activity before
expressing it. Most students found this exercise difficult or
impossible to effect, and, in my experience, all students acting as
subjects in this activity found it very frustrating to attempt and
complete. Another, classic, demonstration entails asking a subject
to fold her arms in the most natural manner to her (i.e., left or
right arm on top of the other), asking her to switch her arms’
position, and finally instructing the subject that the original,
habitual position must never be the one expressed in future. Most
subjects recognize how difficult, if not impossible, such a change in
habit would be.
While
a postdoctoral fellow in population genetics at Harvard, I had an
opportunity to speak with Skinner twice, one of the highlights of my
academic career. At that time, I understood that Skinner
acknowledged factors endogenous to the organism (e.g., genes,
neurons) to be important but that factors inside the “black box”
were not required to predict animal (including human) behavior. As a
former research assistant to M.E.P. Seligman and a student of
Behavioral Ecology, in addition to Biopsychology, I considered myself
prepared to discuss with Skinner the relationship between radical
behaviorism and Darwinism. I found, however, that, in our
conversations, Skinner essentially repeated his ideas presented in
his paper, “selection by consequences,” whereby an organism’s
history of rewards or reinforcements determine its success or failure
in interaction with the biotic (including social) and/or abiotic
environments.
While
it is likely that Skinner had little interest in speaking with me,
thus investing few ideas and fewer minutes in our meetings, I think
that I would have been able to detect in his comments the ability or
willingness to distinguish between proximate (immediate) and ultimate
(evolutionary) factors and between natural (who lives and who dies)
and sexual (who reproduces and who does not) selection. To my
knowledge, Skinner’s canon represents a literature of results
demonstrating the precursors and effects of proximate causation, and
the great psychologist may not have considered in depth the potential
relationship between immediate causation as represented by operant or
responding conditioning and its consequences for survival, ecological
and reproductive competition, and lifetime reproductive success
(“fitness”). Skinner seems to have overlooked the significance
of measuring not only the results of his laboratory programs, in
particular, schedules of reinforcement, but also which conditions
impacted long-term success of his subjects compared to other
conspecifics in the same situations, including identifying what
endogenous and exogenous traits were responsible for individual
consequences subsequent to reinforcement or punishment, as well as,
identifying which behaviors and behavior patterns are genetically
correlated and which vary within and between populations.
The
influence of operant conditioning as a component of the Panopticon
network is, perhaps, best symbolized by Seligman’s “learned
helplessness” experiments. Indeed, this psychologist’s work
utilizing aversive stimuli (electric shock) with canine subjects is a
classic in its genre, becoming a highly successful model for
depression, a mood disorder, and major psychopathology. In the late
phase of his career, Seligman seems to have become more of a clinical
researcher and theorist rather than a mainstream basic scientist.
Nonetheless, his apparent transition highlights the close
relationship between experimental and clinical psychology as nodes in
the Panopticon Network since Seligman’s work highlights the
fundamental role played by basic research as a generator of applied
projects. Foucault’s Panopticon “continuum” and the Panopticon
Network posited in the present text, emphasize what Foucault, with a
degree and teaching experience in psychology, discussed as “power,
knowledge, and discourse.” It is unfortunate that Foucault did not
deconstruct clinical psychology, cognitive psychology, and “radical
behaviorism”, including their relationships to one another, in an
attempt to provide a deep (structural linguistic as well as semantic)
understanding of each. It would have been interesting to determine,
also, Skinner’s, Seligman’s, and other psychologists’ responses
to Foucault.
No comments:
Post a Comment